Connect
MJA
MJA

Cardiopulmonary resuscitation - time for a change in the paradigm?

Michele Levinson and Amber Mills
Med J Aust 2014; 201 (3): 152-154. || doi: 10.5694/mja14.00012
Published online: 28 July 2014

Summary

  • Cardiopulmonary resuscitation (CPR) is the default treatment in hospital unless there is a decision to the contrary and this is documented in the patient record.
  • The outcome of CPR in older chronically ill patients is very poor and discharge home is unlikely.
  • Fewer not-for-resuscitation (NFR) orders are written than there are patients who would not benefit from CPR.
  • NFR orders appear to be a marker of death, rather than the result of informed discussion about end-of-life care.
  • There is a legal and ethical framework for the consideration of the suitability of CPR.
  • Discussions about CPR are challenging, and uncertainty is introduced because of the lack of consensus around futility, the emotionally charged nature of the topic, misconceptions about the success of CPR and the failure to recognise that not offering CPR will allow a peaceful and supported death.
  • Discussion around CPR can be misconstrued as a need for consent. A focus on patient and family involvement may result in an expectation that CPR is an entitlement.
  • As part of evidence-based patient-centred care, CPR should only be offered to those for whom it is beneficial.
  • CPR should no longer be the universal default. We propose an opt-in model, which will drive discussion and evaluation of the efficacy and suitability of CPR for the individual.
  • A CPR discussion should occur on admission for all elderly hospital inpatients.

Since the description and implementation of cardiopulmonary resuscitation (CPR) as a lifesaving procedure in the 1960s, it has become the default treatment for all patients dying in hospitals around Australia unless documentation of a not-for-resuscitation (NFR) plan or order is recorded in the patient's file. At the same time, the number of elderly patients with geriatric syndromes admitted to Australian hospitals has increased. Use of CPR and NFR orders is of particular relevance to this group as they have poor survival and outcomes following resuscitation.1 The aim of this paper is to question whether all patients should receive CPR as a default treatment.

NFR documentation can take many forms, from a handwritten comment by a doctor in the patient's file to a form specifically designed for the purpose. The procedure is also referred to as do not resuscitate (DNR) and do not attempt to resuscitate (DNAR). For the purposes of this article, it will be referred to as NFR. Most NFR forms include a section that records whether the NFR decision has been discussed with the patient or the patient's family. In some cases there is a need to declare whether the patient is competent to make a decision about CPR. Australian data on the prevalence of NFR forms in inpatient histories show that only a minority of older general medical patients have NFR documented in their history.2

Survival to discharge after CPR in the chronically ill older hospital population is poor — less than 6%. Discharge home (as a post-CPR outcome) has decreased without a change in overall survival.3 A significant proportion of those who survive to hospital discharge die within the first postdischarge month. Orotracheal intubation during cardiac arrest, age, premorbid residence in a nursing facility and more comorbid illness predict a poor outcome from CPR.4-6

Several studies have shown that up to one-quarter of all medical emergency team (MET) calls result in a new allocation of NFR status or an assessment that this would be appropriate. In 90% of cases there was agreement between the primary care clinician and the MET assessment of suggested NFR status. In an Australian study, patients who had a limitation of medical treatment instituted by the MET had a hospital mortality of 52%.7,8 NFR orders are implemented only for a minority of hospital patients who are unlikely to benefit from CPR.2 When NFR orders are written for general medical inhospital patients, they tend to be written for those already recognised as dying or at high immediate risk of death. NFR orders seem to be functioning as an indicator of imminent death. A lack of NFR orders may preclude attention to appropriate end-of-life care9 and exposes the patient to a potentially brutal unsuccessful intervention that is highly likely to increase the patient's suffering.10

There is a legal and ethical framework for consideration of CPR based on futility, non-maleficence, beneficence, autonomy and the law.

Futility

A medical professional is under no obligation to provide treatment where no benefit at all would be conferred; however, the meanings of benefit and futility are highly contested. Willmott and colleagues state that the meanings of futile and futility are uncertain in law, and that greater clarification is required.11 They define treatment as futile when there is medical consensus to this effect. Although there is often consensus among the treating doctors that an older chronically ill patient is unlikely to survive CPR, the decision not to offer CPR on the grounds of futility could still be legally challenged. There is no standard Australian guidance on how to achieve consensus, who should participate in it or how consensus should be documented. In the event of dispute about futility, those close to the patient may test the medical practitioner's determination of futility in the Supreme Court.12 This is likely to undermine the medical practitioner's confidence in invoking futility as a reason to withhold CPR. Similarly, the Canadian Joint statement on resuscitative interventions (update 1995) does not define futility but does encourage involvement of the patient in determining futility, although lack of competence or delirium will hamper participation.13

The presence of poor prognostic factors may be sufficient to consider CPR futile before cardiorespiratory arrest occurs. We have included a list of some circumstances where a judgement of futility may be made (Box 1). In other instances, futility can only be ascertained at the time of cardiac arrest, through relevant factors such as asystole and pulseless electrical activity.5,6 Regardless, we argue that physicians be encouraged and supported to make a deliberate decision about resuscitation, rather than rely on the default approach.

Non-maleficence

A medical professional is under obligation to ensure they do no harm, and this often entails a balance between benefit and futility of treatment. Hayes suggests that the decision to withhold CPR in the medically unwell but not imminently dying patient is a judgement about providing an unsuccessful treatment which incurs harm by denying the patient a peaceful death.9

Following a technical medical judgement that CPR would not benefit and may harm in this situation, a CPR-related “deliberative discussion” with the patient and family is important in order to prevent harmful misunderstanding, as they may expect CPR to be performed. If the patient or family disagree with the health care team, there needs to be an ethical decision made weighing up the harm to the patient by providing CPR with the harm to the trust between the patient and family and the health care provider by not providing CPR. The loss of trust may compromise ongoing care. In the case where the patient is expected to survive CPR but have a poor outcome or for whom the outcome is uncertain, Hayes recommends an “interpretive discussion” about the value of CPR for the individual patient. The efficacy of these discussions can be seen in the improved end-of-life care and outcomes for patients and their families.14

Sources of disagreement between the patient and family and the health care provider may relate to lack of trust in health care staff; an overestimation of the success of CPR in the community, likely informed by the media portrayal of CPR; and the influence of community education which emphasises the provision of CPR as first aid.9,15 Religious and cultural beliefs that regard the sanctity of human life as paramount are likely to drive a CPR decision if there is any perceived potential for a deathbed miracle. However, many other treatment options within the practice of medicine are not offered to patients on the grounds that the treatment would not confer benefit or incur harm.

In the case of the sick, older frail patient, not providing CPR can be considered fulfilling the principles of beneficence and non-maleficence.

Consent and autonomy

Doctors have a professional, ethical and legal obligation to enable a patient to provide informed consent to or refusal of treatment. A patient's consent may be regarded as informed if it is voluntary and made with knowledge and understanding of the material benefits and risks involved.16 Notification to the Medical Board may result from failure to meet the requisite duty of disclosure. A breach of this duty causing harm may expose the doctor to liability in negligence.

It is clearly not possible to obtain consent from the patient for CPR at the time of need as by definition the patient is dead or near dead. CPR is provided on the understanding that it is an emergency procedure. However, patient autonomy can be preserved using advance care directives and communication with medical staff.12 Older patients are less likely to choose a burdensome treatment such as CPR if they understand that the probability for survival is low and if the outcome is poor functional outcome or cognitive impairment.17-19

The situation involving a cognitively impaired or demented older adult is more complex. Under Victorian law, and each state differs, only a guardian with the power to make medical decisions or person holding an enduring power of attorney (medical) can make a decision on behalf of the incompetent patient to withhold treatment.20 Patient-centred health care encourages the involvement of the patient and family in health care decisions. Discussions about hypothetical imminent death are highly charged, and patients may find the discussion about CPR challenging and feel that they are not able to engage in it; or alternatively, may strongly wish to engage. Heyland and colleagues showed that seriously ill patients and families do not want inappropriate life-prolonging measures, and that most wanted a shared decision-making role in discussions of end-of-life care.17 However, families often confuse the NFR discussion with consent seeking rather than information sharing. This is confounded further when the treating doctor is uninformed of the legal issues and abdicates responsibility for the decision to the family.21 Policy requiring patients and family to participate in the decision about the provision of CPR can imply that CPR is an entitlement. This reinforces the idea of the primacy of patient autonomy even in the situation where the medical determination is that CPR would be unsuccessful. This dilemma is not infrequently experienced in clinical medicine and is well described.22

In the case vignette (Box 2), an attempted resuscitation attempt is doomed to failure as maximal medical therapy had been instituted in a patient with severe comorbid conditions and poor physiological reserve. The resuscitation attempt would be considered futile (see Box 1). The patient's daughter is not by law entitled to demand treatment considered futile by the treating physician. The physician is either inexperienced with the law relating to the provision of futile or burdensome treatment, and/or is unwilling to commence a process of confrontation and escalation that will be unpleasant, difficult and perhaps not relevant to the current admission and may expose him or her to a legal challenge. The patient survived to discharge without a need for a resuscitation attempt. The difficulty was avoided but not resolved as it will be an issue at the next admission.

Many studies point to significant barriers to the completion of the documentation of NFR orders even in situations where it is recognised that it may be medically appropriate or aligned with the patient's preferences. Beliefs relating to the success of resuscitation vary across medical specialties, which may influence the willingness of the treating doctor to initiate discussion about CPR.7 Discussion of NFR orders can be time-consuming, particularly where there is a perceived infringement of patient autonomy.23 Patients with chronic medical conditions are less likely to have resuscitation orders discussed than patients with cancer, and there appears to be less recognition of the illness trajectory in older people.24

Providers of medical care are bound to provide care that has a reasonable chance of success associated with a low risk of harm. We believe it is time to re-evaluate the status of CPR as the de facto default for all patients dying in Australian hospitals. It is time to regard CPR as a medical procedure like any other that should be offered only to those patients for whom it is likely to be beneficial.23,25 Removing the default for the chronically ill older inpatient in favour of opt-in will drive discussion and evaluation of the efficacy and suitability of CPR for the individual. This should routinely take place on admission.

The way forward

There are legal, social, administrative and knowledge barriers to “de-prescribing” CPR. We need open community discussion about end-of-life care. The discussion should demystify death and raise the situation-related efficacy of CPR and the importance of available community supports for death with dignity. Legal clarity is required for the concept of futility. Although medical and nursing professional bodies endorse the legal position of treatment consent and refusal and the concept of burdensome care in their published documents, the concepts are not yet part of the wider community conversation. Leadership from senior clinicians and legal counsel is needed to facilitate open discourse. Patient-centred evidence-based care demands that the role of CPR in Australian hospitals is reviewed. We believe that CPR should no longer be considered the universal default for all patients, and encourage debate.


Photo by John O'Flaherty, courtesy of Cabrini Health.


Provenance: Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.

  • Michele Levinson1
  • Amber Mills1

  • Cabrini-Monash University Department of Medicine, Monash University, Melbourne, VIC.


Correspondence: mlevinson@cabrini.com.au

Acknowledgements: 

We acknowledge and thank Bebe Loff (Director, Michael Kirby Centre for Public Health and Human Rights, Monash University) for her comments and assistance with the draft manuscript.

Competing interests:

No relevant disclosures.

  • 1. Paniagua D, Lopez-Jimenez F, Londoño JC, et al. Outcome and cost-effectiveness of cardiopulmonary resuscitation after in-hospital cardiac arrest in octogenarians. Cardiology 2002; 97: 6-11.
  • 2. Shanmuganathan N, Li JY, Yong TY, et al. Resuscitation orders and their relevance to patients' clinical status and outcomes. QJM 2011; 104: 485-488.
  • 3. Ehlenbach WJ, Barnato AE, Curtis JR, et al. Epidemiologic study of in-hospital cardiopulmonary resuscitation in the elderly. N Engl J Med 2009; 361: 22-31.
  • 4. Cooper S, Janghorbani M, Cooper G. A decade of in-hospital resuscitation: outcomes and prediction of survival? Resuscitation 2006; 68: 231-237.
  • 5. Weil MH, Fries M. In-hospital cardiac arrest. Crit Care Med 2005; 33: 2825-2830.
  • 6. Di Bari M, Chiarlone M, Fumagalli S, et al. Cardiopulmonary resuscitation of older, inhospital patients: immediate efficacy and long-term outcome. Crit Care Med 2000; 28: 2320-2325.
  • 7. Jones DA, Bagshaw SM, Barrett J, et al. The role of the medical emergency team in end-of-life care: a multicenter, prospective, observational study. Crit Care Med 2012; 40: 98-103.
  • 8. Micallef S, Skrifvars MB, Parr MJ. Level of agreement on resuscitation decisions among hospital specialists and barriers to documenting do not attempt resuscitation (DNAR) orders in ward patients. Resuscitation 2011; 82: 815-818.
  • 9. Hayes B. Clinical model for ethical cardiopulmonary resuscitation decision-making. Intern Med J 2013; 43: 77-83.
  • 10. Wallace CK. In-hospital cardiopulmonary resuscitation [letter]. N Engl J Med 2009; 361: 1708.
  • 11. Willmott L, White B, Parker M, Cartwright C. The legal role of medical professionals in decisions to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining treatment: Part 3 (Victoria). J Law Med 2011; 18: 773-797.
  • 12. Stewart CL. Legal perspectives on consent in disputes about futile care. Med J Aust 2013; 198: 225-226. <MJA full text>
  • 13. Joint statement on resuscitative interventions (update 1995). CMA policy summary. CMAJ 1995; 153: 1652A-1652F.
  • 14. Walling AM, Asch SM, Lorenz KA, et al. The quality of care provided to hospitalized patients at the end of life. Arch Intern Med 2010; 170: 1057-1063.
  • 15. Jones GK, Brewer KL, Garrison HG. Public expectations of survival following cardiopulmnary resuscitation. Acad Emerg Med 2000; 7: 48-53.
  • 16. Australian Medical Council. Good medical practice: a code of conduct for doctors in Australia. www.amc.org.au/index.php/about/good-medical-practice (accessed Apr 2014).
  • 17. Heyland DK, Dodek P, Rocker G, et al. What matters most in end-of-life care: perceptions of seriously ill patients and their family members. CMAJ 2006; 174: 627-633.
  • 18. Murphy DJ, Burrows D, Santilli S, et al. The influence of the probability of survival on patients' preferences regarding cardiopulmonary resuscitation. N Engl J Med 1994; 330: 545-549.
  • 19. Fried TR, Bradley EH, Towle VR, Allore H. Understanding the treatment preferences of seriously ill patients. N Engl J Med 2002; 346: 1061-1066.
  • 20. Office of the Public Advocate. Advocacy and decision-making in relation to medical and dental treatment and other health care. http://www.publicadvocate.vic.gov.au/file/file/PracticeGuidelines/medical_practice_guideline_December%202010.pdf (accessed Apr 2014).
  • 21. Murphy BF. What has happened to clinical leadership in futile care discussions? Med J Aust 2008; 188: 418-419. <MJA full text>
  • 22. Le BH, Chapman MD. Competence and capacity at the end of life: uneasy paternalism. Med J Aust 2011; 195: 476-477. <MJA full text>
  • 23. Brauner DJ, Grusin SL. In-hospital cardiopulmonary resuscitation. N Engl J Med 2009; 361: 1708.
  • 24. Mitchell SL, Black BS, Ersek M, et al. Advanced dementia: state of the art and priorities for the next decade. Ann Intern Med 2012; 156 (1 Pt 1): 45-51.
  • 25. Ehlenbach WJ, Curtis JR. In-hospital cardiopulmonary resuscitation. N Engl J Med 2009; 361: 1708-1709.

Author

remove_circle_outline Delete Author
add_circle_outline Add Author

Comment
Do you have any competing interests to declare? *

I/we agree to assign copyright to the Medical Journal of Australia and agree to the Conditions of publication *
I/we agree to the Terms of use of the Medical Journal of Australia *
Email me when people comment on this article

Online responses are no longer available. Please refer to our instructions for authors page for more information.