Connect
MJA
MJA

Ethical issues in pandemic planning

Adrienne Torda
Med J Aust 2006; 185 (10): S73. || doi: 10.5694/j.1326-5377.2006.tb00713.x
Published online: 20 November 2006

Scenario 1 presents a possible starting point for an outbreak of pandemic influenza in Australia. Ethical issues arise from measures such as quarantining all passengers and crew, isolating the patients in particular wards within the hospital, shifting other patients, designating appropriate medical staff to manage and diagnose the illness in the three unwell passengers, and procuring and using antivirals for treatment of the patients and possibly for prophylactic administration to others who have been exposed. Specific issues raised by this scenario include the need for measures to protect the public, such as restriction of movement of individuals, resource reallocation, duties of health care workers to care for these patients, and use of restricted resources.

Experience with previous epidemic health emergencies, such as the severe acute respiratory syndrome (SARS), has shown that, without a clear ethical framework and an understanding of the decision-making process, decisions may not be readily accepted either by health care workers or by other members of an affected community,1 and may result in long-term psychological repercussions such as anxiety, post-traumatic stress disorder, and depression. Fear, uncertainty of infection and stigmatisation were also problems experienced by health care workers.2,3 In formulating plans to deal with epidemic crises, most countries have acknowledged that many aspects of the response are value-laden.4 Certain core values of our community, such as equality, liberty and privacy, may be challenged or re-prioritised by pandemic planning. The overall approach of the plan will aim to protect the greatest number of people in society from becoming unwell, and keep society functioning as optimally as possible (but even this aim has been challenged5). Individual liberties may be sacrificed for the health of the public overall. This may involve measures such as home quarantine, banning public meetings, or even significant disruption to normal life. If a pandemic did occur, many aspects of the management plan, such as rationing of antivirals and vaccines, occupational risks to health care workers and their families, compulsory vaccinations of certain workers, cessation of many normal health services, and quarantine measures, would also raise major ethical issues.6

Following the SARS experience, a working group of bioethicists in Canada identified core values that are important to consider in relation to pandemic planning (Box 1).7

Exploration of ethical values
Duty of care and reciprocity

Health professions have codes of conduct or ethics which guide the conduct of workers. Generally, these codes identify, either explicitly or implicitly, the concept of “duty of care”,8-10 but they are moderately silent on the issue of duty of care in the face of significant personal risk.11 There are many definitions of duty of care, but the concept generally refers to the duty of a health worker to provide care for and protect patients from harm. In these codes, duty of care is considered in isolation, and does not take into account other duties an individual may have.

The notion of duty of care is important, as it potentially raises many questions during a pandemic. Health care workers were disproportionately infected during the SARS outbreak,12 even once infection control precautions were instituted. In view of the personal risk, health professionals will have to balance the duties and demands of their work against their duties to protect (or even care for) their family, their other patients, other health professionals, and their own health. Some still consider the duty of health care workers to patients to be imperative;12 others feel it to be modified by other duties.13 There is also increasing discussion about the tension caused by conflicting duties of health care workers, particularly now that the concept of work–life flexibility in medicine also appears in many of these codes and oaths.11-14 Choices made during a pandemic may not necessarily comply with traditional definitions of duty of care. Health care workers may decide that the personal risk from caring for infective patients is too great and refuse to do so. This then raises concerns about personal liability and possible negligence. Most of the evidence from the SARS pandemic has shown that the most effective approach to management of health care workers required strong leadership, with leading by example, open discussion with workers, adequate information, protection, and voluntariness in terms of allowing health care workers to decide the level of risk that is acceptable to them and reallocating workers as necessary.15

This issue links directly with the concept of reciprocity. During a pandemic, health workers and others will face a heavy burden in terms of workload, in providing care and protecting the public. There may be many other effects ranging from anxiety, domestic discord and concern, through to loss of income and discrimination.15 Society, government bodies and health care institutions will need to be aware of these issues and develop appropriate ways of providing optimal support (financial, physical and emotional) to workers “at the coalface”, and their families.

Stewardship, trust and solidarity

Stewardship, trust and solidarity are closely interwoven. Stewardship refers to the notion that decisionmakers need to act ethically and in the interests of the individual and the population. This requires good, informed decision making and high levels of trust from both those involved in providing care and the public. Inherent in this is the need for open and clear communication. Acting ethically requires that decisions are made against clear and open criteria.

This is closely allied with the idea of trust. Before, during and after a pandemic, high levels of trust between health workers, their patients and decisionmakers are needed. This requires transparency and openness.

Within Australia, solidarity refers to unity and collaboration between institutions, governments and professional organisations. Communities at every level need to show both solidarity and resilience to minimise the impact of an epidemic.

More broadly, solidarity refers to developing a sense of global collaboration. Again, this is already occurring, but will need to continue to be enhanced.

Discussion

Cognisant of these values, the pandemic plan broadly aims to minimise loss of life and minimise social disruption. Achieving these aims will not be easy, and will largely depend on striking a balance between the needs of the individual and the public as a whole, often dependent on the stage of the pandemic and the measures that need to be enacted. To plan perfectly for such an unknown situation is impossible, despite the resources being put into this. A rapidly changing social and medical situation combined with a possible lack of resources (in the form of antivirals, vaccines, and health workers), combined with widespread fear, will be difficult for all members of the community. A pandemic would bring with it shocks, surprises, unplanned situations and, quite possibly, distress.

Clarity and transparency of decision making will be vital, as will thorough and efficient communication to the public. During a pandemic, many unknown factors will result in decisions being made on scant information, and perhaps changing frequently. The principles outlined in Box 2 are already being incorporated into the ongoing work and decision making of the National Influenza Planning Committee.

In a case like Scenario 2, few people’s lives would be unchanged. Measures to increase social distancing and limit mass gatherings would be considered and possibly enacted. Mass vaccination would be performed as soon as possible. Antivirals would be used according to particular prioritisation guidelines. Many doctors and nurses may refuse to care for infected patients because of the personal and family risk. Long hours, stringent infection control procedures, and isolation may take their toll on volunteering health care workers, who will need to be replaced. Policies, protocols and public health measures may need revision almost daily. Meanwhile, information needs to be disseminated as rapidly as possible both to those in the health industry and to the general public.

One can see how Scenario 2 contrasts with Scenario 1, in terms of pushing the balance towards the need for enforcement of fairly radical public health measures. Major resource reallocation and redistribution of limited resources (manpower and antivirals) would be necessary.

Although Scenario 2 may seem unlikely, it is possible. For this reason, the ethical issues that could arise all need to be anticipated and discussed by a group of informed and interested parties who understand the problems, recognise the ethical issues, and can discuss them in relation to the possible scenarios that may be faced in the event of a pandemic.

Conclusion

In the event of an influenza pandemic, many of the values we take for granted will be challenged. In trying to maximise preparedness for such an event, attempts have been made to identify some of the ethical issues that will arise and the relevant core values to allow discussion of the challenges. These issues need to be discussed by groups of medical practitioners, ethicists, lawyers, infrastructure managers, and members of the community now, to try to assist decision making during a pandemic, even if the decision making is still difficult. This should allow transparency and understanding of the process of pandemic planning, and ensure room for accountability, consultation and review as information and events unfold in a pandemic.

  • Adrienne Torda1

  • Department of Medicine, University of New South Wales, Sydney, NSW.


Correspondence: a.torda@unsw.edu.au

Competing interests:

None identified.

  • 1. Bernstein M, Hawryluck L. Challenging beliefs and ethical concepts: the collateral damage of SARS. Crit Care 2003; 7: 269-271.
  • 2. Maunder R, Hunter J, Vincent L, et al. The immediate psychological and occupational impact of the 2003 SARS outbreak in a teaching hospital. CMAJ 2003; 168: 1245-1251.
  • 3. Hawryluck L, Gold WL, Robinson S, et al. SARS control and psychological effects of quarantine, Toronto, Canada. Emerg Infect Dis 2004; 10: 1206-1212.
  • 4. Jiwani B. Ethics and influenza pandemic planning. Edmonton: Provincial Health Ethics Network, 2001. http://www.phen.ab.ca/pcons/docs/Ethics_&_Pandemic.pdf (accessed Oct 2006).
  • 5. Emanuel EJ, Wertheimer A. Who should get influenza vaccine when not all can? Science 2006; 312: 854-855.
  • 6. Wynia M, Gostin L. Ethical challenges in preparing for bioterrorism: barriers within the health care system. Am J Public Health 2004; 94: 1096-1102.
  • 7. Upshure REG, Faith K, Gibson JL, et al. Stand on guard for thee. Ethical considerations in preparedness planning for pandemic influenza. Toronto: University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics, 2005. http://www.utoronto.ca/jcb/home/documents/pandemic.pdf (accessed Oct 2006).
  • 8. Hippocratic oath — classical version. NOVA Online. http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/doctors/oath_classical.html (accessed Oct 2006).
  • 9. World Medical Association. International code of medical ethics. http://www.wma.net/e/policy/c8.htm (accessed Oct 2006).
  • 10. Australian Medical Association. AMA code of ethics 2004. http://www.ama.com.au/web.nsf/doc/WEEN-5WW598 (accessed Oct 2006).
  • 11. Rudeman C, Tracy CS, Bensimon CM, et al. On pandemics and the duty to care: whose duty? who cares? BMC Med Ethics 2006, 7: e5.
  • 12. Emanuel E. The lessons of SARS. Ann Intern Med 2003; 139: 589-591.
  • 13. Torda A. How far does a doctor’s ‘duty of care’ go? Intern Med J 2005; 35: 295-296.
  • 14. McNeill PM, Dowton SB. Declarations made by graduating medical students in Australia and New Zealand. Med J Aust 2002; 176: 123-125. <MJA full text>
  • 15. Rambaldini G, Wilson K, Rath D, et al. The impact of severe acute respiratory syndrome on medical house staff: a qualitative study. J Gen Intern Med 2005; 20: 381-385.

Author

remove_circle_outline Delete Author
add_circle_outline Add Author

Comment
Do you have any competing interests to declare? *

I/we agree to assign copyright to the Medical Journal of Australia and agree to the Conditions of publication *
I/we agree to the Terms of use of the Medical Journal of Australia *
Email me when people comment on this article

Online responses are no longer available. Please refer to our instructions for authors page for more information.