Connect
MJA
MJA

Addicted to the good life: harm reduction in chronic disease management

Bradleigh D Hayhow and Michael Peter Lowe
Med J Aust 2006; 184 (5): 235-237. || doi: 10.5694/j.1326-5377.2006.tb00209.x
Published online: 6 March 2006
Chronic disease

There is good evidence that lifestyle change is the most effective way to minimise the health burdens of many chronic diseases.1 Unfortunately, individual clinicians can take only limited responsibility for lifestyle interventions, and doctors probably overestimate their role and responsibility in obtaining lifestyle outcomes in individual patients.2

If patients are unwilling or unable to change their lifestyle habits, there are still ways to reduce the harms associated with their choices. For instance, a 50-year-old smoker with blood pressure of 140/85 mmHg and cholesterol level of 6 mmol/L may obtain as great a reduction in cardiovascular risk from the daily use of an angiotensin-converting enzyme (ACE) inhibitor and a statin as he would from giving up smoking.3 Ideally, patients would take up both interventions, but for those who are unwilling to give up smoking, it seems reasonable at least to reduce associated harms by using medications. In our terminology, the use of statins and ACE inhibitors to decrease the cardiovascular risks of smoking would be a harm reduction strategy.

Similar strategies may reduce risk in other people with chronic disease who are unwilling to make lifestyle changes: an obese person who will not decrease his or her food intake can decrease the risk of developing ischaemic heart disease by substituting foods high in omega-3 fatty acids; a person with impaired glucose tolerance can decrease the chance of developing diabetes by using metformin rather than by lifestyle change; and a person with diabetes and poorly controlled blood sugar can reduce the risk of disabling microvascular complications through ACE inhibitor therapy and regular eye screening — even in the absence of better sugar control.

These strategies are already common in clinical practice. We believe that explicitly acknowledging that they are part of a harm reduction strategy allows us to escape from the “best-practice” paradigm with people for whom best practice is impractical.

Ethical considerations

From colleagues, we have encountered both theoretical and practical objections to the application of harm reduction strategies in chronic disease. As clinicians we wish to focus on practical issues, but we also acknowledge our theoretical assumptions.

We have characterised harm reduction as a valid strategy for managing habits of behaviour that we regard as inevitable. However, in applying harm reduction strategies to those who are unwilling, rather than unable, to change their habits, a critic may suggest that a mere preference for unhealthy behaviour violates the notion that such behaviour is inevitable. Our position is that such behaviour is, in practice, inevitable as long as patients have the opportunity to exercise free choice. We have also chosen to defer to the traditional notion that a clinician’s primary ethical obligation is to their patient.

Objection 1: Harm reduction is wrong because it condones or even promotes unhealthy behaviour

Some people feel that tolerance of unhealthy behaviour is tantamount to its promotion. One formulation of this argument holds that harm reduction strategies may perpetuate the unhealthy habits of individuals by lessening the suffering that results from their behaviour. This notion is easily dealt with because the alternative is paradoxical: people can hardly be better protected from the unpleasant consequences of chronic disease after they have already suffered those consequences. This is one reason that we feel it is useful to adopt a perspective focusing on the consequences of behaviour, rather than the behaviour itself.

A more subtle formulation of this argument holds that, by tolerating unhealthy behaviour in some people, we encourage it in others. Objections of this sort are particularly common in the context of drug addiction, where harm reduction programs are said to broadcast implicit messages to the broader community encouraging illicit drug use. We feel that such arguments highlight a need to distinguish health care of the population and of the individual. At the population level, it is true that we ought not to promote unhealthy lifestyles. But at the individual level, there is no need for encouragement of a healthy lifestyle to exclude support for established health problems.

The obligation to focus primary care on individuals supports the idea of harm reduction for those who will not change their habits.

Conclusions

There is currently tension in clinical medicine between the ideologies of evidence-based best practice and disease self-management. This conflict is practical: while some patients will both want and accept disease management that accords with evidence guidelines, others will prefer to negotiate regimens that accommodate their existing lifestyle preferences (see case study, Box 1).

We have argued that the paradigm of harm reduction may offer an appropriate alternative way of thinking about people who are unwilling or unable to adopt particular changes of lifestyle. It is important to emphasise that we are not suggesting that doctors cease to promote healthy changes in lifestyle, or cease to regard those changes as best practice, if the evidence supports such claims. We believe that all patients deserve the opportunity and support to make beneficial choices. We are simply emphasising that patients need to make these choices for themselves, and that it is not wrong to adopt other treatments if the evidence-based best treatments conflict with patient values.

In practice, clinicians should initiate any elements of best practice that patients will accept. However, once clinicians become aware of the limits to patients’ willingness to undertake lifestyle change, they should put aside the lifestyle interventions that patients refuse and consider strategies for harm reduction. They should then continue to monitor patient preferences and renegotiate health care goals as those preferences evolve (Box 2).

  • Bradleigh D Hayhow1
  • Michael Peter Lowe2

  • Flinders University, Northern Territory Clinical School, Royal Darwin Hospital, Darwin, NT.


Correspondence: 

Competing interests:

None identified.

  • 1. Knowler WC, Barrett-Connor E, Fowler SE, et al; Diabetes Prevention Program Research Group. Reduction in the incidence of type 2 diabetes with lifestyle intervention or metformin. N Engl J Med 2002; 346: 393-403.
  • 2. Fiore MC, Novotny TE, Pierce JP, et al. Methods used to quit smoking in the United States. Do cessation programs help? JAMA 1990; 263: 2760-2765. Erratum in: JAMA 1991; 265: 358.
  • 3. Royal Australasian College of General Practitioners (RACGP). Smoking, nutrition, alcohol and physical activity (SNAP): a population health guide to behavioural risk factors in general practice. Melbourne: RACGP, 2004.
  • 4. Kramer P. Listening to Prozac. New York: Viking, 1993.

Author

remove_circle_outline Delete Author
add_circle_outline Add Author

Comment
Do you have any competing interests to declare? *

I/we agree to assign copyright to the Medical Journal of Australia and agree to the Conditions of publication *
I/we agree to the Terms of use of the Medical Journal of Australia *
Email me when people comment on this article

Online responses are no longer available. Please refer to our instructions for authors page for more information.